52 Authors: Week 19 - Etienne Gilson
05/11/2015
Etienne Gilson (1884-1978) was a Christian philosopher. Between the publication of his PhD thesis in 1909 and his last works of philosophy in the late 1960s, he helped to create genuine historical research in Mediaeval philosophy and theology, he wrote dozens of sparkling works of history and of philosophy, and he pugnaciously championed the influence of Christian faith on philosophical reason.
Gilson’s great achievement was to make the theology and philosophy of Saint Thomas Aquinas interesting to people who are not trained Thomists, or professional scholastics. Back in the 19th century, Pope Leo XIII had pushed forward a revival of Thomism with his encyclical Aeterni Patris (1879). Between 1879 and 1914, the ‘Leonine’ revival of Thomism made Thomism fascinating to an elite handful of seminary professors, deeply boring to hundreds of seminarians the world over, and a ‘Name’ which stood for ‘Dry’ to everyone else. To the ordinary folk, Thomas was Saint Trés Sec. The seminary professors were intoxicated by the very thought that Thomas’ ideas had been bottled in the Middle Ages and were thus free from the impurities of rationalism, of empiricism and of German romanticism. Bottled so long ago and laid up in the ancient Cathedral vaults to await the thirst of modern times, Thomas’ thought was, the professional scholastics claimed, not merely of its own time, not just ‘Mediaeval,’ or ‘Vintage 1255’ but a perennial wisdom which existed outside and beyond the temporal vicissitudes of philosophy and theology.
Gilson was born in Paris in 1884. He had deep roots in Burgundy and a love of the Romanesque Cathedrals of that region, like Vézelay. Once when I tried to probe one of his surviving Toronto colleagues about where Gilson stood in a dusty quarrel of the 1950s, the old man stonewalled by saying, ‘all Gilson and I ever talked about was wines and cheeses’. Gilson brought the mediaeval thinkers like Thomas and Bonaventure and Scotus to life for his non-scholastic contemporaries. He did this by treating the mediaevals, especially Thomas, not as ‘marble’ exemplars of perennial truths but as living teachers who address our modern conundrums. By the way, Gilson would not like like this line in eulogy. He called himself as a paleo-Thomist, and saw his own approach to Thomas as very different from that of Jacques Maritain, the self described ‘apostle of saint Thomas for modern times.’ Gilson’s approach to Thomas was much more rooted in Thomas’ texts than that of Maritain. He did not put words into Thomas’ mouth or put anachronistic questions to Saint Thomas and invent answers for them.
But nonetheless, Gilson perceived the connecting threads between ancient and modern problems. He was beloved in the secular bastion of the Sorbonne, where he taught for fifty years, invited to give prestigious lectures at Harvard, in Indiana, at Princeton and at Aberdeen (where he gave the Gifford lectures) and read by his educated contemporaries because he brought the mediaeval ‘Age of Faith’ to life before their eyes. He was a genuine philosopher, driven by authentic fire to know, and he communicated his delight in thinking things through from first principles.
In the 1940s and 1950s, Gilson was prized by the secular Universities for his defence of the compatibility of faith and reason. In those same years, many of his Catholic peers amongst the professional Scholastics regarded him as as unduly fideist, too prone to insist upon the theological sources of the reasoning of Christians like Thomas Aquinas. And this was the paradox: those very Scholastics insisted upon Thomas’ Aristotelianism with a view to ensuring a hearing for Thomas amongst the seculars, and yet it was the ‘fideistic’ Gilson who brought Thomas, and even Aristotle, to life for his contemporaries. Gilson claimed that Thomas’ thought does not simply rest on Aristotle’s reasoning: rather, Thomas turns the ‘water’ of Aristotle’s philosophical thinking into the wine of theology. Gilson said, in 1959:
Christian mystery ... does not follow reason, it precedes it, accompanies it as it moves along; it wraps it round and eventually shows it salutary perspectives which reason left to itself would never suspect possible. ….I rememb[er] a passage in ... Thomas’ Commentary on the De Trinitate of Boethius. St. Thomas was (even then) being accused of pouring the water of philosophy into the wine of Holy Scripture. He replied simply that theology was not a mixture in which a constituent kept its own nature. A theologian doesn’t mix water with wine, he changes water into wine. We ought not to be disturbed by this manifest allusion to the miracle at Cana. St. Thomas is speaking for all theologians conscious of the supernatural function they are performing.
Gilson argued over and again that, that, as a theologian, Saint Thomas turned the water of philosophy into the wine of theology. Theology is not watery wine - wine with a little bit of the water of reason thrown into it. It is water transformed into wine by the touch of faith.
[Ed.: This is my own copy of a Gilson book, the only one I own, unread these many years. Now I'm inspired to read it.]
Which of Gilson’s books should you read? Some of his books are for the professionals, such as Being and Some Philosophers or – I would say – The Christian Philosophy of Saint Thomas Aquinas. I love both of those books but it is difficult to imagine someone reading them purely for the pleasure of it, without intending to write a paper or an essay about them. Some of Gilson’s writing is dated, like his book about Dante. Some of his philosophical writing is too difficult for amateurs and some of his history writing is out of date. Nonetheless, a surprising number of his books remain in print, and some of his books are still being translated from the French down to the present. Here are two or three books by Gilson which many people with a taste for philosophy could enjoy.
The Unity of Philosophical Experience was given at Harvard in 1936 for the ‘William James’ lecture series. It is about a series of ever graver assaults on the possibility of metaphysics – at the hands of psychologists who reduce metaphysics to psychology, worshippers of mathematics who think maths explains everything, ‘theologists’ who reduce metaphysics to theology (making God everything and nature nothing) and ‘sociologists’ who reduce metaphysics to the study of society. And yet, every attempt to kill metaphysics and replace it with some supposedly higher discipline (sociology, psychology, mathematics, even theology) fails: metaphysics defeats its ‘undertakers’ because, Gilson argues, questions about being and reality will not lie down and die on command. Philosophical experience is rooted in reality, in existence. The laws which unify philosophical experience root it in existence. Existential questions, or questions about being, ‘what is,’ are the ones which drive metaphysics. Existence is a vital reality which is larger than any of the tombs prepared for it, by the particular disciplines like psychology or sociology. I have never succeeded in describing The Unity of Philosophical Experience without making it sound more difficult than it is. It is a bit like C.S. Lewis’ A Pilgrim’s Regress: it’s about a series of reductionist attempts to say ‘metaphysics is ‘really just’ something smaller than the effort to respond to being as a whole.
I first read The Unity of Philosophical Experience as an undergraduate, and I thought it was a history book, detailing the decline of philosophy as a result of a sequence of disasters, beginning with theologism, with its nominalism and voluntarism, on through the psychologism of William of Ockham, the Mathematicism of Descartes, the moralism of Kant and on to the ‘sociolatry’ of Comte. A little later I came to ‘Grad School’ in the States and was taken aback by the venom with which a CUA graduate responded to my reference to Gilson. Like me, he had mistaken The Unity for an historical narrative. Unlike me, he was sufficiently sophisticated to be repulsed by the one sided caricatures of Avienna, Scotus, Bonaventure, Descartes and Kant which he found in it. In fact, Gilson says very clearly that the Unity (and likewise Being and Some Philosophers and God and Philosophy) are not history books at all, but works of philosophy. As in A Pilgrim’s Regress, the figures which Gilson treats are ‘allegorical,’ meant to stand in for certain tendencies or ideas. The ‘Ockham’ or the ‘Scotus’ of The Unity is not the real, three-dimensional Ockham or Scotus, but one aspect of those thinkers, studied from very close up and detached from the wider body of their thinking. I give The Unity of Philosophical Experience as an example of a book which any educated person could enjoy because it deliberately simplifies and paints a philosophical story in primary colours. The reason Gilson’s books have lasted is his aesthetic sense, his ability to paint a picture which draws the eye to the center of events, their existential core.
The Spirit of Mediaeval Philosophy is Gilson’s ‘Gifford Lectures’, given at Aberdeen in 1931-1932. Starting with the apologists and Athenagoras, and running right down to the Franciscan Scotists and William of Ockham himself, Gilson argues that the ‘spirit’ of mediaeval philosophy is Christian faith, and that this faith enabled it to delve deeper into existence and its mysteries than any previous human thinking. Now, I’m a theologian and I use words like ‘delve’. But what Gilson means to say is that the theological genesis of mediaeval philosophy enables it to argue and reason to intellectual heights which had never hitherto been assaulted. The philosophers of the Middle Ages believed themselves to be living in a created cosmos. This enabled them to perceive that things are good, that they are oriented towards ends, that they are knowable, and above all, that things exist in and of themselves.
Living in a cosmos they believed (from Genesis) to have been freely created in time by God, the mediaeval philosophers woke up each morning feeling lucky to be alive. So they noticed that things are not just in here (as concepts), and not just out there (as objects) but exist, as individual acts of being. Every existent thing is like a ‘one off’ art work: it exists at all not just because stuff is out there but because God created it. God does create kinds of things – he does a line in trees, say, and a range of fish. But that there are kinds and ranges of things is not just a given, because God creates natures and kinds of things by making them exist. The mediaeval philosophers were able to notice existence because they could ‘see the Masters hand’ working in and through their ‘sacramental cosmos’.
The Spirit of Mediaeval Philosophy is a book length defence of the influence of Christian faith on philosophy. It is a defence of the possibility of ‘Christian philosophy,’ the product of believers’ reasoning. The old Heineken advertisments used to claim that this beer ‘reaches parts other beers cannot reach’. This is Gilson’s claim for philosophizing within a Biblical, sacramental cosmos: it will reach parts other philosophies cannot attain. Faith gave the Christian thinkers the ability to articulate the metaphysical, existential intuitions common to all humanity. The Spirit is not a ‘faux history book which is a philosophy book in disguise. It is a genuine history of mediaeval thought which uses that history in defence of the possibility of a fruitful and provocative relation of faith to reason.
Thirdly, I would recommend Painting and Reality. Well, I would doubt that any one who does not work in a university would have the time to read Gilson’s Painting and Reality from beginning to end. A few chapters of it would suffice. This is the book in which Gilson combines his great aesthetic sense with his interest in existential questions. He studies art and painting as examples of pure acts of ‘existing’ which come forth from their creator’s hands as physical objects, as ‘kinds of things’ and as ‘existential personae’, characters in the drama of existence. Gilson stresses that paintings do not merely flow from concepts in their maker’s minds, but physically, from the maker’s hands. Many of the people who read this blog would enjoy a few chapters of this master piece.
—Grumpy is a professor of theology in the Midwest.
I tried Gilson in college, for a special paper on medieval political thought, and found him pretty dry himself. At the time he didn't strike me as a good ambassador for medieval philosophy, since I really rather enjoyed reading John of Salisbury, Aquinas, Dante, Ockham, and Marsilius of Padua, but would never have guessed how exciting they were from reading Gilson. I might give him another go now though.
Posted by: Paul | 05/11/2015 at 03:26 PM
I went to graduate school in Toronto, where the ghosts of Gilson and Maritain still haunt the campus. Every autumn there are second-hand booksales at the university, mostly selling off donations from alumni, and books by those two pop up with relatively high frequency. Over the years I've amassed quite a collection. Sad to say, I've read only a handful of those many volumes.
I can add a vote, though for The Unity of Philosophical Experience, which I found both accessible and interesting. I tried Being and Some Philosophers but it defeated me. I started The Spirit of Medieval Philosophy years ago and didn't finish it for some reason, but I'd like to finish it someday.
I will agree with Grumpy that Gilson is a good tutor for those interested in Aquinas. Next to Josef Pieper -- and next to Thomas himself, of course -- it is Gilson who has taught me most about the value of Thomas' thought.
Posted by: Craig | 05/11/2015 at 03:54 PM
The reason I'd never even made an attempt to read the Gilson book pictured here is that I thought it would somehow be cheating to read it without having read Thomas himself. I've now admitted to myself that I'm never going to read Thomas, at least not in any quantity. I'm not sure whether it therefore makes more or less sense to read the Gilson book.
At any rate this is probably not the best Gilson book for an amateur to read, but it happens to be the one I have.
Posted by: Mac | 05/11/2015 at 05:34 PM
I have been meaning to read Madame Bovary in French for about 25 years. I cannot read it in English. It's a rule I've invented for myself. It looks like I may never read it until I retire...
About 15 years ago I cracked and read 'The Red and the Black' in English. I loved it.
Posted by: grumpy | 05/11/2015 at 07:09 PM
I'll soon find out how many of those when-I-retire plans I carry through. I blush to admit that I've never read MB. Started it once, got distracted, never got back to it.
Posted by: Mac | 05/11/2015 at 09:18 PM
I bought a copy of 'The Unity of Philosophical Experience' about 10 years ago but have never read it. Seems like I grabbed the right one to start with, although obviously it isn't particularly helpful just sitting on the shelf.
Posted by: Rob G | 05/12/2015 at 04:38 PM
That is true of way too many books that I own.
I found this reference to Maritain interesting: "He did not put words into Thomas’ mouth or put anachronistic questions to Saint Thomas and invent answers for them."
I've read a bit of Maritain, and liked it, but I did sometimes wonder if he was doing something like this.
Posted by: Mac | 05/13/2015 at 10:07 PM
I don't quite understand the place of St. Thomas in RC thought. Does he hold a similar place to that of Augustine, in that everything prior to him is in a sense filtered through his thought? It doesn't seem possible to me for a Catholic to be "non-Augustinian." Is it possible to be a "non-Thomist"?
To put it another way, we Orthodox generally consider our thought to be "patristic," the idea being that any post-Schism Eastern writers/thinkers simply continued the patristic "line." In the West, it seems that you have the same mentality, the difference being that all Patristic thought comes to be filtered through, and thus focused in, St. Thomas.
In the East we really don't have one thinker who holds that sort of role, of the type of either Augustine or Thomas. We have theologians who might be said to typify the Tradition, but none who are seen as coalescing and codifying it like the two I mentioned.
Posted by: Rob G | 05/14/2015 at 06:26 AM
I'm not really qualified to answer that. But I'll give you my impression, which is that it's definitely possible to be a non-Thomist. I think Thomas is favored but not imposed or even ubiquitous. I think there have been a number of non-Thomist theologians of recognized stature since the early 20th c. who were well regarded and approved.
Posted by: Mac | 05/14/2015 at 08:33 AM
Aquinas has always been a big part of Western academic theology, but in terms of Catholicism more generally his eucharistic hymns are probably the most important thing he wrote. He ridiculed the Immaculate Conception, so clearly not everything is filtered through him. There are reams of mystical theology that owe nothing to him at all. It's possible to be a perfectly good Catholic without ever having heard of him, and I don't think there's a single theological issue aside from transubstantiation where Aquinas adds to the Fathers (and what he adds is mental tools for grasping what the Fathers already held). In terms of academic disciplines, both philosophy and theology owe a lot to him (often more than either is willing to admit), and in terms of intellectual method he is exemplary.
Posted by: Paul | 05/14/2015 at 10:12 AM
Well, in the US, most people were taught from the Baltimore Catechism from 1885, I see, until after Vatican II. As I have gotten older and read more of the Summa here and there, and read people who are Thomists, I see that the Baltimore Catechism must have been largely written by Thomists. So there is a huge influence here.
AMDG
Posted by: Janet | 05/14/2015 at 11:10 AM
I like what you said there, Paul, about Aquinas. I never read a word of him until I was at least 40, but I managed to know and practice the essentials of the Faith for more than 20 years before that.
Now, though, if I have a question, I will sometimes remember to go to the Summa online and look up the relevant question. I find this pretty helpful and usually enlightening.
Janet, I think you're right about the Baltimore Catechism.
Posted by: Louise | 05/14/2015 at 03:04 PM
I do not know the answer to Rob G's question. It seems to me that the Vatican I constitution Dei Filius was written by Thomists and its difficult to assent to it unless one assents to some Thomistic thinking. It is about how God is known by reason via external evidence and by faith via external evidence.
After Aeterni Patris it looked like Thomism was the 'official philosophy' of the Church - the encyclical does contain the injunction, 'go to Thomas!'
The popes of the period of the Modernist Crisis in the early 20th century likewise not only exhorted folks to ite Thomae but instructed that only Thomism could be taught in seminaries.
Gilson wept with pleasure when he heard Paul VI say that the Church is open to all philosophies which are compatible with the Church's dogma - he was a Thomist who did not like Thomism being an 'official philosophy' or treated as if it were dogma.
Posted by: Grumpy | 05/14/2015 at 09:34 PM
" but instructed that only Thomism could be taught in seminaries."
I'm really not sure that most of us understand how much of what we know comes from Thomas, and this is one of the reasons.
Louise,
You say that you knew and practice the essentials of the Faith without knowing Thomas, but you really don't know what you knew of the essential was informed by Thomism.
AMDG
Posted by: Janet | 05/14/2015 at 09:40 PM
I don't have time to look for it, but there was a recent George Weigel column about Newman in which he discussed Newman's role in encouraging renewed interest in the Fathers.
Posted by: Mac | 05/14/2015 at 10:17 PM
Everything Grumpy says is true, but I should point out that Thomism was the only *philosophy* taught in seminaries - not the only *thing*. And seminarians weren't for the most part training to be philosophers. And it meant that everything taught as philosophy in seminaries had "Thomist" on the box, even when the contents had little to do with Aquinas.
Newman was shocked at how little awareness of Aquinas there was among Catholics in the 1840s. At some point between then and Aeterni Patris, things must have changed somewhat.
Posted by: Paul | 05/15/2015 at 01:16 AM
Thanks, guys. Very helpful.
To frame my query in another way, in talking with several educated Catholic friends, I sometimes get the impression that they believe that the East, whether EO or Byz. Catholic, isn't really patristic, or perhaps patristic enough so to speak, because it's non-Thomistic. In other words, to be truly patristic one has to be Thomistic, since Thomas not only "gathers" the thought of the Fathers, but uniquely and indispensably epitomizes them.
Posted by: Rob G | 05/15/2015 at 05:39 AM
Certainly one of the ways Newman encouraged knowledge of the Fathers was by translating Aquinas's Catena Aurea into English. But as long as Eastern churches recognise the Latin Fathers and Bede, I'd have thought they were patristic enough for anybody ...
I'm all in favour of Thomism, but I think it gets more lip-service than actual adherence in Catholic circles (while being both praised and blamed for 19th-century tenets and habits of thought that have very little to do with it).
Posted by: Paul | 05/15/2015 at 10:15 AM
Well Paul I don't think it's true that Thomas' thought was the only *philosophy* taught in seminaries. There were manuals of theology too, eg manuals about the Trinity, and I think those manuals were Thomistic.
Of course I agree that much of what was taught as Thomism was 'Thomism'.
I am not a Thomist. I am a follower of Hans Urs von Balthasar, a fellow who is regarded as heretical by many Thomists.
But I do not think it is right to underplay the importance which Thomas' thought has had for the Western Catholic Church.
Posted by: grumpy | 05/15/2015 at 10:05 PM
Grumpy, I think you might have reversed the polarity of my statement about philosophy. I didn't say that Aquinas was only taught as philosophy, but that it was only in philosophy that Thomism had any sort of monopoly. I'll add that that monopoly was a relatively recent and relatively short-lived phenomenon.
Prior to the 1870s Aquinas was one influential voice among several, with a number of schools in which other voices predominated. This isn't to say he wasn't influential, and certainly not to say that he didn't deserve to be influential, but to suggest that he was the only influential thinker, let alone the only permissible one, is a terrible distortion of reality.
Much as I favour Thomism, I think its importance is exaggerated by viewing it from the aftermath of its brief official dominance: up to the mid-19th century any real acquaintance with the writings of Aquinas (except, as I said in my initial comment, his eucharistic hymns) was pretty much confined to universities (where he had no sort of monopoly) and to Dominican and Jesuit houses of study.
Almost from the very beginning the manuals used in seminaries (and the catechisms used in Sunday schools) were deeply influenced by Spanish and Jesuit late Scholasticism, but these were only "Thomist" in a very limited sense.
Posted by: Paul | 05/16/2015 at 04:03 AM
Well I'm thinking that Rob G asked that question like butter would not melt in his mouth and his intention was to set the Catholics wrangling amongst themselves.
Gilson was amongst the first, perhaps the first, publically to distinguish the Thomism of Thomas Aquinas from the Thomism of 'the commentators' - the Sixteenth, Seventeenth, Eighteenth century 'schools' of Thomism. I don't presume to know if he was right or not. I have being reading Thomas for more than thirty years, but I'm not a Thomist or a Thomist expert. And I know that some Thomists agree with Gilson and some Thomists do not. The leading Thomists today do not, but maybe they are wrong. I'm finding it more and more difficult to say that the Thomisms of the 16-18th century were simply not Thomism at all. I'm more inclined at least these days to say Thomas can be read in many ways. And Gilson himself fully acknowledged this, when, at the end of 'Reason and Revelation in the Middle Ages' he spoke of 'The Thomist Family'. The Thomist family includes all those who take Thomas as their teacher, and who are, Gilson says, inclined to give a reason for their theological assertions, that is, never to say 'this is purely a matter of faith'.
Is the Catholic Church a 'Thomist family'? That is the question Rob has set us to discuss. In one sense, Paul is right that the dominance of Thomism is a largely 19th century thing - its influence on Vatican I (an ecumenical Council), and on Aeterni Patris, and its subsequent influence on seminary teaching for just under a hundred years. This teaching didn't only affect professors of philosophy and theology in seminaries. It trickled down into way Catholics thought about their faith as a whole.
Is it dead and gone now? I do not think so, at least in terms of magisterial teaching. Fides et Ratio gives four models of a Christian thinker: Edith Stein, Etienne Gilson, Jacques Maritain, and Rosmini (who had to be culled from the Index by Ratzinger a couple years before ...).
I think that if you look at the model of the use of faith and reason in Fides et Ratio overall, a kind of Augustinian-Thomist reasoning is very plain. I would call it a Gilsonian encyclical, but I do not wish to enter into a debate about that.
As far as influence on seminary teaching, and on teaching lay people who work in the Church is concerned, I do not think any modern theology (von Balthasar, de Lubac, Rahner, etc) which has not 'made its peace' with Thomism will make headway and become central. It will have to take Thomas serious and include it within its 'modern synthesis'. So in that sense, I have partially to disagree with Paul and say that I think Thomism is and remains unavoidable for Catholics.
Posted by: Grumpy | 05/16/2015 at 07:31 AM
I meant to put a :) on my comment about Rob G ! :) Too early in the morning to be posting
Posted by: Grumpy | 05/16/2015 at 07:39 AM
I may be wrong, but it seems to me that all these small Catholic Colleges like TAC, Ave Maria, Christendom, etc., are very Thomist. They are small, but this is where the priests, sisters, theologians and Catholic philosophers are going to come from in the near future. So, I think the church in the US will become increasingly Thomist.
AMDG
Posted by: Janet | 05/16/2015 at 09:02 AM
Yes but I dont think it is only that the more consevstive students and seminarians are thomist. I think that even those who do not see themselves as Thomist want to abdorb his thought not bypass it
Posted by: Grumpy | 05/16/2015 at 10:02 AM
I would like to say something longish but am on my phone, so: there seems to be an impression among the Orthodox that Thomas has a problematic near-dogmatic position in Catholicism. I took Rob's question as coming from that. And it kind of is a problem.
I'm sure we've all had the experience of being exasperated by amateur Thomists who apply his method in a maddeningly mechanical way. I don't especially want to see more of that. Sounds like Gilson can be a corrective to that.
Posted by: Mac | 05/16/2015 at 10:09 AM
Yes he is and I see that our response to Rob G should have included something like: sectarian thomism is exists within the RC church but is not canonized by that church.
But I still think that the place of Thomas and of the various Thomistic traditions in the RC church is wider and deeper than Paul suggestd
Posted by: Grumpy | 05/16/2015 at 11:14 AM
want to abdorb his thought not bypass it
I'm trying to figure out if abdorb was supposed to be absorb, or adore or something else.
AMDG
Posted by: Janet | 05/16/2015 at 11:26 AM
"Well I'm thinking that Rob G asked that question like butter would not melt in his mouth and his intention was to set the Catholics wrangling amongst themselves."
Yes, and I would have gotten away with it if it weren't for you meddling philosophers!
"there seems to be an impression among the Orthodox that Thomas has a problematic near-dogmatic position in Catholicism. I took Rob's question as coming from that."
Right - some Catholics seem to talk as if Thomism has that sort of position, while others do not. That divergence is what I was wondering about.
"sectarian thomism is exists within the RC church but is not canonized by that church."
Makes sense.
Re: Rosmini, please see the excellent newly translated book by the late Augusto Del Noce, The Crisis of Modernity. Del Noce, who died in 1989, was one of the premier Italian political philosophers/cultural critics of the post-WWII era. He argues that Rosmini represents the culmination of an alternative, "positive" line of modernity that parallels the negative one that culminates with Nietzsche. According to Del Noce both lines begin with Descartes but end in opposite places, one in nihilism, the other in Rosmini's "refined" theism that has faced the criticisms of atheism and come out the other side better for it.
http://www.mqup.ca/crisis-of-modernity--the-products-9780773544420.php
I got the softcover on Amazon for about $30 (the hardback lists for $100!)
Posted by: Rob G | 05/16/2015 at 12:47 PM
Yes Im reading Del Noce's book right now as it happens and translating another.
Janet: absorb
Posted by: Grumpy | 05/16/2015 at 01:10 PM
"Im reading Del Noce's book right now as it happens and translating another"
Which one?
Posted by: Rob G | 05/16/2015 at 02:38 PM
We are creating an anthology called 'Downhill All the Way: Telling the Story of Atheism'. The idea of it is that there is a *kind of* general Catholic story about the origins of atheism - see the Preamble to Vatican I ! - but beyond that there are lots of versions or takes on this story. So we begin with von Drey and Staudmaier, and then we have Kleutgen and Gunther and Brentano for the later nineteenth century, and then for the early twentieth century we have Gilson and de Lubac and Hans urs von Balthasar (from The Apocalypse of the German Soul). For the second half of the twentieth century we have Cottier and del Noce. We are translating a bit from a book called 'The Problem of Atheism'. We are just translating lots of little bits of these authors. Or not so little - about 80 pages is the max.
Posted by: grumpy | 05/16/2015 at 04:50 PM
At a party this afternoon I proposed Rob G's question (neutrally worded) to two graduate students in Theology - one who studies medieval vernacular theology and an Old Testament exegete. They straight away fell into a surprisingly heated debate on almost exactly the same lines as Grumpy and I have been differing along here.
Posted by: Paul | 05/16/2015 at 05:03 PM
I don't think three Catholics, even of quite similar persuasions as we are, would state the place of Thomas in the Church in exactly the same way.
I mean, how many people are there who are Christopher Derrick fans? Not many. And yet the two of us, both of whom who qualify for that small segment, don't quite interpret what Thomas means to the Church in the same way.
The evidence is ambiguous. How does one interpret that Vatican I is clearly the work of Thomists? What is the status today of Aeterni Patris? What does it signify that Fides et Ratio as a 'Gilsonian flavour' ?
If its too strong to say its ambiguous, its not crystal clear either.
Posted by: grumpy | 05/16/2015 at 05:32 PM
Aeterni Patris versus Paul VI's Decree on Priestly Training, which came out of Vatican II--
From Aeterni Patris:
From Decree on Priestly Training: Those seem very different takes on the role of Thomism. Or is it just a change in language?Posted by: Marianne | 05/16/2015 at 06:06 PM
Something that was mentioned this afternoon that chimes with what Janet says was this: that academic job ads for scholars of medieval theology in the US invariably require an ability to teach Thomism. This is not the case in Europe.
I did wonder whether it was a coincidence that both the people taking the position that Aquinas's influence is relative and late are Benedictine-educated historians of periods when Aquinas was known but did not serve as the sole exemplar of scholastic theology.
Posted by: Paul | 05/16/2015 at 06:27 PM
Before Nicaea Trinitarian theology was ante Nicene
Posted by: Grumpy | 05/16/2015 at 07:40 PM
Had Rob G asked "So, this Thomas Aquinas, is he important?" my answer would have been a resounding Yes. But his actual question was "Is it possible for an RC to be a non-Thomist?" – to which the answer also has to be a resounding Yes.
The same does not apply to Nicaea.
One of the things I like best about Fides et Ratio is that it puts Bonaventure alongside Aquinas (while Dante's Paradiso puts Siger of Brabant, of all people, alongside St Thomas in heaven). I owe more to Thomas than to any of the others, but the historical reality is that Thomas is not all of Thomism, and Thomism is not all of Scholasticism, while to be a Catholic does not require adherence to any of the above (and does require one to reject Aquinas's views on the Immaculate Conception).
Posted by: Paul | 05/17/2015 at 04:45 AM
Fides et Ratio refers to Bonaventure. But the way it envisages the synthesis of faith and reason is that if an Augustinian Thomist such as Gilson.
Posted by: Grumpy | 05/17/2015 at 11:18 AM
"Well I'm thinking that Rob G asked that question like butter would not melt in his mouth and his intention was to set the Catholics wrangling amongst themselves."
Yes. Evil man. :)
"I'm sure we've all had the experience of being exasperated by amateur Thomists who apply his method in a maddeningly mechanical way."
I think I must have led a very sheltered life! And that I must be pretty dumb. I have no idea what Grumpy and Paul are talking about! This is very funny.
Posted by: Louise | 05/17/2015 at 02:38 PM
I did understand this:
"At a party this afternoon I proposed Rob G's question (neutrally worded) to two graduate students in Theology - one who studies medieval vernacular theology and an Old Testament exegete. They straight away fell into a surprisingly heated debate on almost exactly the same lines as Grumpy and I have been differing along here."
That's really funny. :)
Posted by: Louise | 05/17/2015 at 02:41 PM
That anthology sounds fascinating, Grumpy.
Well, on Thomas, now that I'm totally confused....
Just kidding. It all makes sense, actually, as in Anglo-Orthodoxy we've got a somewhat similar situation vis a vis Gregory Palamas.
Posted by: Rob G | 05/17/2015 at 03:12 PM